Home > Uncategorized > The representative agent — a theoretical cul-de-sac

The representative agent — a theoretical cul-de-sac

from Lars Syll

anwar-shaikh-1Rigorous macroeconomics must therefore ground its analysis in individual behavior, recognize that only a few key variables carry over to the aggregate level, and generally posit distinct functional forms at the macro level. Keynes and Kalecki are eminent examples of this. Keynes builds his analysis of aggregate consumption on personal income and a variety of subjective and objective factors that influence individual savings (non-consumption) behavior. He is also careful to note that institutional and organizational factors play an important role. Despite all of this, he only requires that aggregate real consumption be a function of real income with the property that the marginal propensity to consume be less than one. Kalecki’s theory of price follows a similar path from micro to macro. It begins with an equation for the price of an individual firm which depends on the relative size of the firm, its sales promotion apparatus, the union power of its employees. Yet the industry price level has a different function form, tied to a reduced set of variables consisting of the industry’s average unit costs and average degree of monopoly power (through which all others variables are expressed) … Similar paths can be traced in Marx, Schumpeter, and many other great economists. Macroeconomic analysis was already rigorous before it was diverted by neoclassical analysis into the theoretical cul-de-sac of a hyperrational representative agent.

Since there will generally be many micro foundations consistent with some given aggregate pattern, empirical support for an aggregate hypothesis does not constitute empirical support for any particular micro foundation … The question, of course, is why on earth would one insist on deriving policy implications from foundations that deliberately misrepresent actual individual behavior?

Anwar Shaikh

Yes indeed, why would one derive policy implications from something that is nothing but a convenient untruth? And still, mainstream economists seem to be impressed by the ‘rigour’ brought to macroeconomics by New-Classical-New-Keynesian DSGE models and its rational expectations and representative agent micro foundations!

It is difficult to see why.

Take the rational expectations assumption. Rational expectations in the mainstream economists’ world imply that relevant distributions have to be time-independent. This amounts to assuming that an economy is like a closed system with known stochastic probability distributions for all different events. In reality, it is straining one’s beliefs to try to represent economies as outcomes of stochastic processes. An existing economy is a single realization tout court, and hardly conceivable as one realization out of an ensemble of economy-worlds since an economy can hardly be conceived as being completely replicated over time. It is — to say the least — very difficult to see any similarity between these modelling assumptions and the expectations of real persons. In the world of the rational expectations hypothesis, we are never disappointed in any other way than as when we lose at the roulette wheels. But real life is not an urn or a roulette wheel. And that’s also the reason why allowing for cases where agents make ‘predictable errors’ in DSGE models doesn’t take us any closer to a relevant and realist depiction of actual economic decisions and behaviours. If we really want to have anything of interest to say on real economies, financial crisis and the decisions and choices real people make we have to replace the rational expectations hypothesis with more relevant and realistic assumptions concerning economic agents and their expectations than childish roulette and urn analogies.

‘Rigorous’ and ‘precise’ DSGE models cannot be considered anything else than unsubstantiated conjectures as long as they aren’t supported by evidence from outside the theory or model. To my knowledge no in any way decisive empirical evidence has been presented.

No matter how precise and rigorous the analysis, and no matter how hard one tries to cast the argument in modern mathematical form, they do not push economic science forwards one single millimetre if they do not stand the acid test of relevance to the target. No matter how clear, precise, rigorous or certain the inferences delivered inside these models are, they do not say anything about real-world economies.

Proving things ‘rigorously’ in DSGE models is at most a starting point for doing an interesting and relevant economic analysis. Forgetting to supply export warrants to the real world makes the analysis an empty exercise in formalism without real scientific value.

The kind of knowledge and information we seek in science is something different from what we look for in fiction. Building ‘fictional’ models that we all know are false — not only in the sense that they idealize or abstract from some things (all models do) — in the sense that no matter how many corrections, amendments or ‘successive approximations’ made, they will never be true of the real-world phenomenon they try to describe or analyze, can’t be the right way to proceed in science. Although that kind of model assumptions (often of a mathematical kind) is necessary from a tractability point of view, they are far from harmless since they usually are not possible to ‘relax.’ What drives them is their exact necessary form without which the sought after results would never obtain. If this kind of economic models — as argued by some economic methodologists — gives us the same kind of knowledge as we get in ordinary fiction, well, then surely we should seriously reconsider what we are doing. Letting tractability, rather than reason, decide what assumptions we make in our theories and models, is not what we need if we want to build a realist and relevant economic science.

Mainstream economists think there is a gain from the DSGE style of modelling in its capacity to offer some kind of structure around which to organise discussions. To me, that sounds more like religious theoretical-methodological dogma, where one paradigm rules in divine hegemony. That’s not progress. That’s the death of economics as a science.

Showing that something is possible in a ‘possible world’ doesn’t give us a justified license to infer that it therefore also is possible in the real world. ‘The Great Gatsby’ is a wonderful novel, but if you truly want to learn about what is going on in the world of finance, I would recommend rather reading Minsky or Keynes and directly confront real-world finance.

The assumptions and descriptions we use in our modelling have to be true — or at least ‘harmlessly’ false — and give a sufficiently detailed characterization of the mechanisms and forces at work. Models in mainstream economics do nothing of the kind.

Our aspirations have to be more far-reaching than just constructing coherent and ‘credible’ models about ‘possible worlds’. We want to understand and explain ‘difference-making’ in the real world and not just in some made-up fantasy world.  Science has to be something more than just more or less realistic ‘story-telling’ or ‘explanatory fictionalism’. You have to provide decisive empirical evidence that what you can infer in your model also helps us to uncover what actually goes on in the real world.  If you fail to support your models in that way,  you come up with nothing that holds as an explanation what goes on in the world in which we live.

Postulating ‘representative agents’ equipped with ‘rational expectations’ may help mainstream economists deriving sought for results like ‘equilibrium’, ‘stability’ and downward-sloping demand curves. But telling us that something is possible in a patently artificial fictional world inhabited by ‘representative agents’ equipped with ‘rational expectations’ is not enough. Showing us that something possibly can happen in a model world, is not enough to explain what actually happens in the real world.

  1. May 16, 2020 at 2:35 pm

    As Always…(:>) Rigorous, Compact, to the Point, Merciless…, and done in the style of Hospital Emergency Wards, without “roundabout” & cumbersome Anaesthesia…, BEAUTIFUL! “Give Thanks & Praises to the Most Hight…!” (BMW)

  2. Edward Ross
    May 17, 2020 at 12:44 am

    Once again thank you Lars and Anwar Shaikh , as a non academic member of the public, i find your above post “The representative agent a theoretical cul-de-sac”
    Echoes and clarifies my simple real world understanding of the real world, that is based on on observations through the eyes of a participant in the real world. Rather than the obvious false assumptions of those academics living in academic ivory towers, isolated from the real world of real people. A further more i think the the above comments , and some recent posts on micro and macro should be a great help for students to understand clearly how the whole subject of micro macro is manipulated to substantiate ideological theoriesTed

  3. May 20, 2020 at 12:35 am

    I agree with the criticism on “representative agent”. Algorithmic Theory is designed to solve the problem, let me explain how I do to it. Every person is assumed to selectively, serially, and repetitively use Instructions to process information to think. Instructions are innately and universally equipped with everyone. After birth, and originally, everyone is identical to each other in minds — because their brain can be assumed empty. While they subsist, information comes in mind and they begin to think, and to generate knowledge as thinking results. As they know nothing or little about the world, they think attentively, subjectively even randomly, therefore leading to different stocks of knowledge which further guide oneself to think and act. Thus, everyone is particular, both similar and distinct in some aspects to another, but due to computational diseconomy, cannot be definitely analyzed. This shall be the meta socio-economic theory, or the “principle”. But, how similar or distinct s/he is? How a real person would be? The answer is: let’s look at the real world. Theories then are bridged to empiricism where the “representative agent” can make sense, but limitedly, and a modeler with theoretical framework and empirical fillings can do anything — as long as the modeler believes his/her study is economical, competitive or effective in comparison with other modelers or practitioners. Welcome to visit my site to see the methodology in detail.

  4. May 23, 2020 at 11:30 am

    “religious theoretical-methodological dogma, where one paradigm rules in divine hegemony”.

    There we have Lars hoist by his own petard, not having looked up in a decent dictionary what ‘dogma’ means, nor looked at its development in religious history.

    “[In Algorithmic Theory] Every person is assumed to selectively, serially, and repetitively use Instructions to process information to think”.

    There we have BinLi forgetting the process of parity checking to detect mis-representations.

  5. Craig
    May 23, 2020 at 9:56 pm

    I begin to think that the present paradigm for legitimate inquiry, namely Science Only, is almost as antiquated and in need of change as the present monetary and financial paradigm of Debt Only. If it weren’t a fact that the monetary and financial paradigm has been unchanged for virtually the entire history of human civilization and the present paradigm of inquiry has only been dominant for the last four centuries that would be true.

    Monetary Gifting and Wisdom. The next two mega paradigm changes.

  1. No trackbacks yet.

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google photo

You are commenting using your Google account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.