Home > The Economics Profession > Confessions of a Serial Liberty-Reducer

Confessions of a Serial Liberty-Reducer

from Peter Dorman

Since I have been placed by Econ Journal Watch in the leading ranks of economists who have signed “liberty-reducing” petitions, I figure I should respond somehow. An obvious first reaction would be, if this is all it takes to be grouped with such distinguished and thoughtful individuals as Jamie Galbraith and Eileen Applebaum (not to mention our own Michael Perelman), please give me more to sign. But maybe I should say something about this idea of liberty-reduction as well. 

The authors openly state that they rely on a single principle to gage liberty, noncoercion by government. By this standard, for instance, an increase in the minimum wage is liberty-reducing, since it increases the number of wage offers that would be criminalized. This is not just a theoretical possibility; in Los Angeles the co-owners of a chain of carwashes were forced to pay over a million dollars to their workers for minimum wage violations, a plea bargain they made in order to avoid long prison sentences. There can be no denying that the minimum wage, whether you favor it or not, has an illiberal aspect.

Of course, the starting point for evaluating the single-minded reliance on noncoercion as the barometer for liberty is normally Isaiah Berlin’s essay, “Two Concepts of Liberty”. Berlin contrasts noncoercion, or “negative” liberty, with “positive” liberty, which enables individuals to make the choices they truly prefer. Berlin’s treatment confuses three different variants of liberty, however, so it is a good idea to put his essay down and think more carefully about the issue. The most precise definition of positive liberty sees it as applicable to the individual level, but pertaining to the feasibility of choosing X (what one prefers) rather than simply the absence of a coercive constraint on choosing X, as negative liberty requires. To the extent that the minimum wage provides more resources for people at the low end of the labor market, so they can enjoy a wider range of choice over access to the necessities and comforts of life, it enhances positive liberty at the expense of negative. (Workers are denied the choice of accepting, and employers the choice of offering, a sub-minimum wage.) I will say in passing that I accept Berlin’s judgment that, of the two, negative liberty is more precious in a wide variety of situations, but I think I can demonstrate that in another set of situations, also quite large, positive liberty can have as much or more “liberty content” as its negative twin. (This is due to the interdependent nature of economic and social life, which can sometimes make the costs of not being supported by others comparable to the costs of being coerced by them—so that the threat of nonsupport becomes coercive.)

Nevertheless, there are still two more types of liberty that have large followings. One is collective liberty, the freedom to engage in collective action on the part of a group with a common identity or shared interests. The great theorist of this notion was John Dewey; see, for instance, his book Individualism Old and New. Economists steeped in game theory should have no problem in understanding why such a conception of liberty is necessary and popular. At an intuitive level, if there is any basis for people conceiving of themselves as a “we” instead of simply a set of “I’s”, there ought to be a corresponding idea of joint liberty. It should also be obvious that there is great potential for abuse if the “we” is insufficiently elective, or if inadequate allowance is made for individual differences within even the most cohesive groups—but all conceptions of liberty are dangerous if they are blind to the others.

The fourth conception arose during the Romantic period in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries and is associated, in the United States, with writers like Emerson and Thoreau. If collective liberty is situated above the level of the individual, “inner” liberty is two levels down: it is about freedom from convention, habit, and any other barriers to the discovery and cultivation of one’s genuine potential. We know this today as the ethos of rock ‘n roll: the role of the singer or guitar hero is not to be the most technically proficient (although this is admired), but to reveal to the audience his or her deepest, most genuine self, a role model for this kind of liberation.

Schooled by Berlin, we often think of tradeoffs between competing notions of liberty, and this is undoubtedly true, but with four distinct possibilities to consider, there may be synergies as well. The case of the minimum wage is instructive. Here is my own story: I came of age during the 1960s, when there was full employment and the real minimum wage was far higher than it is today. Thanks to the counterculture, I took time out to explore different life directions: I spent years in underground newspapers and, later, community radio to see if I wanted to be an “alternative” journalist. I spent a few months trying out the life of a professional chess player. (OK, I was no Ken Rogoff, but I did combine chess journalism, instruction, and competitive play at a lower level.) I also dabbled in other stuff that we can leave to the side right now…. How was this possible? The high minimum wage, I would argue, had a lot to do with it. I felt free to experiment because, at any time, I could find a low-labor-force-attachment job that paid enough to keep me afloat. In other words, the positive liberty I enjoyed thanks to a high minimum wage also enhanced my inner liberty to find myself during the typical finding-oneself years. I think young people coming of age today have a lot less of this freedom, and this is sad.

Closing note: the authors of the EJW article speak of “ideological” biases of economists based on the extent to which they support or oppose the noncoercive conception of liberty. I see it differently. To me, to be ideological is to be unable to recognize the claims of competing points of view. For instance, raising the minimum wage increases some kinds of liberty of some people, and reduces other kinds of others. You strike the balance according to your values and judgment. But a nonideological view demands that you bear in mind that, even though you may think the balance falls on the side of raising the wage floor, this does not cancel out the negative consequences. If a thousand workers are better able to put food on the table, but ten teenagers are unable to get an after-school job of a few hours a week, the benefits to the larger group do not erase the costs to the smaller. Ideological thinking typically means putting on only one set of glasses and disregarding other points of view. Nonideological thinking means being able to live with contradictions.

In this sense, I think the categorizers and not (necessarily) the categorized in the EJW article are the ideologues.

  1. Avner Offer
    September 11, 2010 at 10:29 am

    The champions of liberty never say anything about coercive and asymmetric employment contracts. Freedom hardly exists within employment contracts. no freedom inside the factory gate. This is accommodated into the pretension of freedom by the notion that contracts are freely entered. So if freedom is curtailed by a contract, that is OK. but if initial bargaining power is asymmetrical, than the weaker party has little freedom. And typically, there is no real bargaining – more commonly it is take it or leave it.

    • September 11, 2010 at 3:35 pm

      The more fundamental issue is why there is asymmetric power in employment. Full employment would provide workers with leverage, so the more fundamental question is, why is there not full employment? Is it the the market, or interventions? If it is interventions that prevent labor from being fully employed, it is not ultimately contracts, but imposed governmental costs, that deprive labor of economic power.

  2. s h a r o n
    September 11, 2010 at 2:57 pm

    With regard to “concepts of liberty”, I was awaiting a reference in Dorman’s article to corporations (writ large). An excellent examination of the influence (and conundrum) of the rise of “corporate liberalism” vis-a-vis individual liberty is R. Jeffrey Lustig’s fine and thorough book (now over two decades old) of that title.
    [Warnings: 1. Lustig’s book is not an easy read; 2. It has been impossible for me to put it down, and I am compelled to re-read swaths of it]

  3. September 11, 2010 at 3:31 pm

    “Postive liberty” is misnamed. A minimum wage does not provide freedom to a worker. Higher wages provide economic power. Liberty means an absence of legally imposed coercion, and the legal implementation of moral equality (e.g. equality before the law). “Positive liberty” should be called “subsidized economic empowerment.”

  4. September 11, 2010 at 3:47 pm

    “Nonideological thinking means being able to live with contradictions.”

    Oh, I don’t know about that. I live in contradictions daily and have ideological commitments – since for me, a question like “Does economic system xyz work?” only makes sense when completed with the answer “for whose benefit?” Stripped of its sophisticated George Mason veneer (The Teabagger Intelligentsia), what we got here is Pareto Efficiency as religion: Any change of state that makes at least one person worse off (than “now”) is “liberty threatening” or “liberty reducing”, regardless what ill-liberties there are in the status quo.

    So, when somebody from AIER reads something by Ha-Joon Chang, does his/her head just explode?

  5. Merijn Knibbe
    September 11, 2010 at 4:04 pm

    “A Homerus model of the economy”
    Let’s take a short look at economic history. Around 1900, Dutch horticulturalists founded vegetable auctions to ‘countervail’ the power of traders. They tried to create a more ‘perfect’ market, characterized by more competition between traders and larger volumes, which enabled horticulturalists to obtain better prices and to specialize on a limited number of products. This was successful – to an extent . As horticulturalists were not obliged to sell their products at the auctions, many of them still sold (part of) their production to individual traders (the well known free rider problem) which, as these traders were much better informed about quickly changing market conditions in the cities, influenced prices for the worse (from the view of the horticulturalists). Then, World War I arrived and the government restricted individual selling. As the government needed information on total production, all vegetables and flowers had to be sold at the auction. After the war, when government restrictions on trade were lifted, an unintended consequence of these restrictions was that horticulturalists – who had seen the benefits of the war system – voluntarily agreed to oblige themselves to sell their harvests only at the auction: an “Odysseus and the sirens” solution. What’s freedom?

  6. September 11, 2010 at 7:38 pm

    Quentin Skinner’s contrast between the republican and liberal concepts of freedom in “A Third Concept of Liberty” is interesting in this respect. The collective liberty concept clearly fits into his republican concept.

  7. September 11, 2010 at 10:34 pm

    We can’t speak meaningfully about “liberty” without a referent.
    Increasing one person’s or one group’s liberty usually translates into a decrease in liberty for another person or group.

    • Fred Foldvary
      September 12, 2010 at 5:28 pm

      Liberty means the absence of any restriction or imposed cost on peaceful and honest human action. In liberty, the law prohibits coercive harm to others and allows everything else. Harm is distince from mere offense. If a minority group has been denied religious liberty and then obtains it, this increase in their liberty does not deprive others of liberty. Others may dislike that religious expression, but their being offended does not deprive them of liberty, i.e. the legal right to do any nonharmful act. Free speech may deprive some of happiness, having to put up with speech they dislike, but there is no decrease in their liberty.

  8. September 13, 2010 at 2:29 am

    Please ask a Palestinian or Native American about what happened to their liberty when the new inhabitants decided to increase their own “rights”.

    • September 13, 2010 at 2:57 pm

      Why do you designate the theft of land as “liberty”?
      And why do you claim that such theft is the natural right of the invaders?

  9. September 13, 2010 at 11:44 am

    When we look at the selling price of an item and the need to recover its cost plus a profit to remain in business we not that taxes and minimum wages can be sums not adequately included.

    If there are too few sales we chalk it up to “conditions” — even when, as today, there is a systemic denial of money enough to around.

    If we want higher employee earnings, as we do when we cannot afford constant strife between management and labor, cost plus pricing may be necessary. This, in turn, may necessitate subsidized buyers.

    Or subsidized sellers may b a better answer.

    One thing is for certain, to optimize quality of product and quality of life, we cannot leave the current pricing equations to our habits as they happen to be at the moment–when the moment spells deflation or inflation that will curtail employment, automation, distribution, consumption, etc., as these measure are examined in detail for effect on people today and all their tomorrows.

    Our monetary systems of production have not adapted well to hyper-mass production via automation and other means of rapid replication of the products of industry. Demand is coming up short. But, so is supply, as population growth may explode.

    Is it not time to reduce the adversarial nature of our systems and introduce more full accounting for desired effect and why results must guide our rules and inputs in place of habits of belief, thought and practice that invite persistent failure?

    • September 13, 2010 at 3:06 pm

      Subsidies have to be paid for and incur a double deadweight loss, both on the taxing side (if on production) and on the spending side (the increase in consumer surplus being less than the opportunity cost of the subsidy). Why advocate a subsidy instead of a reduction of taxes on wages? The abolition of taxing wages would substantiall increase take-home wages and increase employment.

  10. Mike Meeropol
    January 24, 2011 at 2:27 pm

    Noam Chomsky tells a story about asking Paul Samuelson (they both taught at MIT) why he had a spectrum of social organizations FREEDOM (unfettered capitalism) followed by various stages of the “mixed” economy — going all the way to COMMUNISM (complete state control of the entire economy. Samuelson then paralleled these real-world examples with different economic approaches — laissez-faire economics on the “freedom” end and Soviet style Marxism on the “state control” end.

    Chomsky noted that if you wanted to model freedom vs. control you’d have to place both America’s corporate dominated society and Soviet Communism on the “non freedom” side and put various anarchist philosophies on the “freedom” side.

    For him it was common sense that the modern corporate dominated society in the US reduces the freedom of workers, consumers and citizens very much in the same qualitatitve way (not the quantitative elements — like mass imprisonment and denial of basic rights on paper in Soviet style communism) as did Soviet-syle communism.

    Samuelson said it was an “interesting” idea and never really responded.

    • Peter Radford
      January 24, 2011 at 4:42 pm

      Mike: Precisely. I love this, and thanks for pointing it out. Corporations have to be co-located with any other central planned economy. Chomsky overstates things only to the extent that the levers of government remain in the hands of the people. Once corporate interests dominate democracy he becomes more accurate. Are we there yet?

  11. Nathanael
    May 13, 2011 at 1:38 am

    Anyone who has to work in order to live is *coerced* into working. So much for liberty. When there is a cartel or large near-monopolies providing the only living-wage employment, this coercion translates directly into “wage slave” conditions: “You take what we offer you, or you starve and die”.

    Somehow, right-wing ideologues like the CJW categorizers never pay any attention to this.

    Legally, contracts made under duress are not valid. Factually, an employment agreement where the employee is at risk of starvation without employment is made under duress. What sort of “liberty” do we have here?

    Any analyst who doesn’t recognize that major economic cartels exert more power than government is simply an ideologue not worth reading.

  12. John Merryman
    September 11, 2012 at 4:25 pm

    Please add an awareness that a person’s life today is continuously bathed from earliest childhood in advertising and that this has (as intended) a huge coercive liberty modifying effect.

  1. No trackbacks yet.

Leave a comment

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.